One of my greatest passions in life is food, trying out new cuisines and spices in unusual restaurants. In a certain way, a love of food was central to my philosophical development; part of the reason I went to work in Bangkok, where I discovered Buddhism, was my love of Thai food.
So I’m interested in philosophical treatments of food. Recent treatises on the subject, though, have proved disappointing. One of the worst is Leon Kass’s The Hungry Soul, a work that tries to think through just about every aspect of eating except for the pleasures of taste. He mentions them very briefly on pp. 90-91, where he dismisses them as ephemeral, disappearing once enjoyed, and therefore “closed to the permanent or the eternal” – just like music or drama, though this parallel goes curiously unmentioned. Kass admits that he “cooks little” and “has unsophisticated tastes” – basically, it would seem, he doesn’t enjoy food very much. Which makes The Hungry Soul comparable to a treatise on music written by the tone-deaf.
But Kass may be a bit too easy a target. He has already been the target of much ridicule on the Internet for his pompous pronouncements on food etiquette, most notoriously his condemnation of the act of licking an ice cream cone, as “a catlike activity that has been made acceptable in informal America but that still offends those who know eating in public is offensive.” I know few who take him seriously.
Far more of a hearing is given to Michael Pollan, whose recent work seems to echo Kass’s puritanism in language more acceptable to educated left-wingers. Especially, his work In Defense of Food seems rather to be an attack on it. Pollan claims that his proposed dietary laws “are conducive not only to better health but also to greater pleasure in eating” (12). But it seems to me that the latter claim is, at best, true only if one shares Pollan’s own bland Western food aesthetic, one I find rather repulsive. Much of Pollan’s attitude to food seems to be targeted against its enjoyment. He is upset that today our “foods are processed in ways specifically designed to sell us more food by pushing our evolutionary buttons — our inborn preferences for sweetness and fat and salt.” (pp. 149-50) Or, to put it a different way, that they’re designed to taste good, to give us pleasure. How catlike.
What should we eat instead? One of Pollan’s cardinal rules for eating is “Don’t eat anything your great grandmother wouldn’t recognize as food.” (148) But what an insipid, washed-out world this advice would create! For those of us whose great-grandmothers were North American WASPs, following this advice would lead us to a diet that is neither tasty nor especially nutritious: primarily bland meat and potatoes. My Canadian great-grandmother would not have recognized Thai fish sauce or habanero peppers or lemon grass as food, any more than she would have recognized Spam or Cheez Whiz. (At least her daughter might have cooked with those!) Pollan, meanwhile, acknowledges that his Jewish-American family’s diet involved “cheese blintzes, kreplach, knishes stuffed with potato or chicken liver, and vegetables that often were cooked in rendered chicken or duck fat.” (3) While this is at least somewhat tastier than the WASPy side, are we really to believe that it is healthier for us than a diet of Lean Cuisine frozen dinners?
Pollan’s next rule strikes me as even more poorly conceived. Here he says to “avoid food products containing ingredients that are more than five in number” – or even “unfamiliar”! (150) This would, at least technically, rule out just about anything I’ve ever cooked, any dish with complex spices – and any attempt to try new and unfamiliar cuisines. Granted, he’s thinking primarily about chemically synthesized ingredients rather than complex Asian court dishes, but his brush strokes are so broad that they include just about every food I can actually imagine enjoying, and he doesn’t seem to care.
Pollan is right about many things, especially at the macro level when he is speaking of politics rather than aesthetics: the industrial food-production system, as it now stands, is harmful to the environment in a large number of ways, unnecessarily cruel to animals, and designed to push unhealthy food choices. These are real problems, and worthy of attempts to fix them through policy. Still, the food that comes out of this system has three great advantages. For one, it is cheap, which makes it possible to feed a great number of people who would otherwise starve. Much like the comfortable housing conditions made possible by concrete cinder-block apartment towers, that affordability is not something to be taken lightly. Second, this food saves us time: a virtue easy to disparage but nevertheless vitally important. Third, this food is intentionally tasty. It’s designed to give pleasure – because that is exactly what those “evolutionary buttons” do.
It’s this last point that Pollan really seems unable to handle. He claims that “we Americans have always had a problem taking pleasure in eating.” But to the extent that this is true, it seems that Pollan himself is a better example of that problem than the presidents he cites as examples of it. While criticizing an American predilection for what he calls “nutritionist philosophy”, he claims “George H. W. Bush’s predilection for pork rinds and Bill Clinton’s for Big Macs were politically astute tastes to show off.” (54) That politicians feign preferences to seem more like their voters is hardly news. But whether sincere or not, what were Bush and Clinton trying to indicate about themselves? That they were practitioners of an austere “nutritionist” ideology that takes no pleasure in eating? Or that they, like their voters, happened to actually enjoy taking pleasure in food that is designed to give it? Designed, that is, to push “our evolutionary buttons — our inborn preferences for sweetness and fat and salt”?
I think the answer to that question is pretty obvious. Nobody eats Big Macs and pork rinds because they subscribe to a scientific ideology of nutritionism. They know Big Macs and pork rinds are bad for them – but they eat them anyway just because they value pleasure in eating, that same pleasure that Pollan dismisses as “our evolutionary buttons”. And they are also rightfully skeptical of a brazen snobbery like Pollan’s, one that takes its own bland aesthetic preferences as a standard of virtue.
What turned my attention to food–I herd–I could try to have to keep a sense of myself when eating (taste and health aside), to promote self observation in natural situations …Seeing myself eating brings about more feeling for life–less thinking about life…
Please let me know if these esoteric notes are to far off topic…
I’ve always taken Pollan’s “rules” to be polemical, but easily adapted for actual real-world use: The “grandma” rule, replaced by *anyone’s* grandma, and the “no more than 5 ingredients” being “cook mostly starting with basic ingredients”. Which is… pretty reasonable if you enjoy cooking your own food and want to be able to do quality control on what goes in.
But I do wonder whether this wave of moralizing about food is a new thing, or whether it is just illustrative of gaps in my historical knowledge.
Moralizing about food has a very long history – see Leviticus! Which, now that I think of it, does have another significant thing in common with Pollan: as far as I can tell, they both infer (illegitimately, I’d say) from aesthetics to ethics. A lot of Leviticus sure seems to come down to “don’t eat this because it’s gross”. Pollan clearly has the boomer-hippie aesthetic that valorizes the “natural” above all else, and wants to enforce that aesthetic on others.
a) Moralizing about food was also in vogue during the late Middle Ages, along the lines of analogy with other moral discourses. In early modern England moralizing about food had a distinctly nationalist and Protestant-work-ethic character: beer was better than sack (fortified wine) because buying beer kept trade within England and was less likely to lead its consumers to avoiding work (or so the Puritans believed). See, for example, the contrast between Falstaff and Prince John in Shakespeare’s Henriad. The nationalist half of this was then turned on its head after the Enlightenment: a nation’s wealth is improved by trade with other nations, so buying foreign goods is the right thing to do; and luxury goods increases the production of capital and encourages workers to work more hours in order to afford them, so it is beneficial to the common good for people to produce and consume luxury goods. Wine therefore becomes morally superior (perhaps) to beer. The manner and conclusions of moralizing about food changes from period to period and place to place… but I don’t think it is new broadly speaking.
b) Although I agree that your amendment to “anyone’s grandma” has a lot arguing for it, I wonder if a secret motive for the grandma rule has to do with familial sentiment or a sense of grounding oneself in a family or national tradition. If you look at my comment responding to Amod Lele responding to Bryan Carr in this thread, you’ll see that some of my own pleasures in food are based on a sense that the food has some ancestral significance. I haven’t read Pollan’s book so I can’t say whether he makes this connection explicit, but I rather suspect that it accounts for some of the rule’s emotional force.
Food is or ought to be a locus of great philosophical interest partly because it is a place where ethics and aesthetics intersect. Like Ted M, I consider Pollan’s rules adaptable if you sub in an archetypal Wise Grandmother rather than a particular historical instance, and make other sensible adjustments as needed. His broader advice — “not too much, mostly plants” — seems basically sound if a bit vague. As for the pork rinds, Big Macs, and etc, I have to differ with you. These do not appeal to some American Gourmet Gusto. They are, frankly, pretty damn awful as gustatory experiences go. Fat and salt by themselves are very, very Lowest Common Denominator. Anyone with a backyard grill knows they can put McD’s to shame. The appeal of processed foods may well be (as you suggest) partly convenience, but my suspicion is that it is also a socioeconomic indicator, a signal of what tribe one belongs to — as are, of course, nouveau cuisine or organic farmers’ market produce, or (now that you mention it) the laws of kosher or hallal diet, among other such practices.
I also don’t have much of a problem with the “not too much, mostly plants” part. I think those work well enough as advice (and are not necesarily even that vague, since he does spell them out in considerably more detail). It’s the “eat food” – because of the breathtaking snobbery attached to the corollary that all the myriad edibles he dislikes are noti food. An extreme indicator of tribal identity.
But as for pork rinds and Big Macs – it would not be hard to produce similarly cheap and convenient food out of vegetables, without deep-frying. They don’t, because these taste better. To my palate, they also taste considerably better than the Pollanist food that one gets at the sort of “New American” restaurant that advertises “fresh local ingredients” – where one is somehow supposed to revel in the supposed earthy deliciousness of unseasoned zucchini.
I have wondered before about the zeal with which nutritionists–I’m thinking here partly of people I know as friends or acquaintances, and partly of people out of “sh*t New Agers say” videos–recommend various juices or leaf vegetables. Is the zeal indicative of actual enjoyment? Of the effort they must put in to convince themselves that they like it? Of a principled evangelical spirit towards nutritionism? Or of an attempt to affirm their membership in a group?
It’s certainly possible to train your palate so that you come to prefer certain combinations of ingredients (or a lack of certain ingredients) with greater nuance and specificity. I have a friend who is particular in her taste in chocolate, and who very much enjoys that chocolate which she enjoys; I, on the other hand, could enjoy any but the worst chocolate, and yet I don’t think I’d enjoy any of it as much as she would enjoy her favourites.
And palates can also be influenced by social and psychological conditions. For instance, although I prefer the taste of Fuzzy Peaches to black licorice candies, I would prefer to receive black licorice candies from my Dutch relatives because I received those from them as a child as souvenirs from Holland. My father is Dutch but I have never been to the Netherlands, and gifts from there always had a sense of both the exotic and the intimate (though I’d never have been able to articulate this as a child): they represent a part of my personal history which remains somewhat alien to me. And so while I don’t normally enjoy the taste of black licorice, I do enjoy it in the specific cases where it means “Dutch family”–and I really do enjoy the taste of it in these cases, though still less so than I enjoy the taste of Fuzzy Peaces.
Is it then possible that someone could train their palate to such an extent that they really do find unseasoned zucchini delicious, so long as the zucchini in question is a good piece of zucchini? Or, differently but similarly, if I accept that pleasure in eating is only partly based on evolutionary pleasure-buttons and is also partly based on social and psychological conditions, then should I also accept that a nutritionist might take pleasure in eating zucchini–might really enjoy the taste of unseasoned zucchini–for social and psychological reasons? Even for reasons I find silly?
And if I accept all of that, is it possible that I could train my palate so that I enjoy the taste of unseasoned zucchini?
And if I can, and if unseasoned zucchini is a better option by other sets of standards–personal health, environmentalism–should I therefore try to learn to prefer unseasoned zucchini? I find the idea *ahem* unpalatable but somewhat convincing.
That smell and taste are an attractive instinct, could lead us to a search of our instinct for food, willfully freeing us from our likes and dislikes to more impartiality-compassion…