Tags
Aristotle, ascent/descent, Four Noble Truths, Martha Nussbaum, Martin Hägglund, religion, Śāntideva
It is typically the case that more can be said in disagreement than agreement. In the case of Martin Hägglund’s This Life, I think paying attention to those realms of disagreement is particularly helpful, because our deepest disagreements highlight the ways in which I am a Buddhist and he is not, even though there are core elements to his critique of Buddhism that I absolutely share.
As is the case in many extended disagreements, it can be helpful to start with a disagreement over terminology in order to make sure that what follows is clear. In Hägglund’s case, he frames his argument as one for a “secular” view over a “religious” one. I have said a great deal over the years about why I think the concept of “religion” generally obscures more than it clarifies, and there’s no need to repeat those general points here; in the present context, the important thing is that Hägglund falls victim to the same problems others do. In Hägglund’s telling, Martha Nussbaum can count as entirely “secular” despite her self-identification as Jewish, while Spinoza, the Stoics and the Epicureans all count as “religious” – even though many Epicureans explicitly rejected the gods. Such a framing, it seems to me, can only end up as the vast majority of other attempts to demarcate the “religious” from the “non-religious” do: in confusion.
However, though the terms “religious” and “secular” are poorly chosen, the conceptual distinction that Hägglund uses those terms to portray is quite a helpful one. He uses them to mean respectively what I have called ascent and descent, and indeed occasionally uses those words himself (p101, for example). What Hägglund is doing is to advocate descent against ascent, and I think the way in which he does so is helpful.
I find it helpful because in many respects my own project is to develop a synthesis between ascent and descent, between what Hägglund would call the religious and secular. I agree with Hägglund’s critique of some core traditional Buddhist doctrines: especially, I agree with him that to sever all attachments would come far too close to death itself as we normally conceive it. The Nyāya and Vaiśeṣika schools are explicit about claiming that liberation is the absence of consciousness; scarcely better is the kind of Buddhism whose only justification for avoiding suicide (or murder, in Mahāyāna) is the fear of a worse rebirth. To fully free yourself from sorrow is also to “free” yourself from joy; “as long as you are attached to someone or something that you can lose, you are susceptible to suffering.” (Hägglund 44) I stand with Hägglund’s descent on all of this, and I recognize that Śāntideva or Buddhaghosa would very much look askance at me for all of that.
But. That is not the whole story, and cannot be. For the first twenty years of my life, before I found Buddhism, I lived completely in such a life of descent, at least as hostile to “religion” as Hägglund ever was. And it was agony. Without the sense of perspective that my encounters with Buddhism would later bring me, I moved from one disappointment to another, filled with impotent rage at the political world, despondent at my lack of romantic prospects, frustrated over trifles. If my only choice was between the life of a monk and that life, I would likely pick the monkhood. A Buddhist monk’s pure ascent is significantly better than a pure descent that embraces our existing cravings without attention to the ways these trap us in suffering.
Dukkhanirodha, the removal of suffering, is of course a core Buddhist idea: the Third Noble Truth. I have previously expressed my objection to Śāntideva’s view that suffering should be prevented because “no one disputes that!” As with John Stuart Mill on why happiness is desirable, the argument does nothing to establish that happiness or the removal of suffering is the only thing properly desirable. We have goals beyond the removal of suffering and we are right to do so.
None of that is to say, however, that the prevention of suffering is not a human goal, or should not be one. Yet the concern to prevent suffering is one Hägglund seems to dismiss. He affirms that human cares and aims constitutively require the possibility of suffering, and says nothing at all that I can discern about wanting to minimize that suffering. He says little if anything about our drives to be happy, joyous, or contented, to reduce the pain and anguish and frustration that most of us experience on a daily basis. In his view they do not seem to matter.
But they do matter. Here it is possible to make a retort to Hägglund on the grounds of Martha Nussbaum, a thinker with whom he has great sympathies. That is: Nussbaum’s Aristotelian grounds for criticizing revisionist views like Śāntideva’s have to do with our phainomena or endoxa, our “prevalent ordinary beliefs”. Aristotle uses language like “we think”, “we praise”, “nobody would choose” in order to refer us back to the beliefs with which we begin our inquiry. Such claims, Nussbaum says, remind an opponent of the “depth and power” of the beliefs he wants us to shed; “it thus places on him the burden of showing why and for the sake of what these beliefs are to be given up.” (Fragility of Goodness 365-6) And surely, indeed, nobody would choose a life with more suffering over one with less, except in certain cases where some other care or aim happens to outweigh it. Such cases are real – but, it seems to me, they are the exception. We do all have a deep and powerful aim to reduce our suffering. That aim can conflict with our other aims, but those other aims shouldn’t automatically get priority, any more than the aim to reduce suffering itself does.
And it is from that need to reduce suffering that ascent (“religious”) views get a great deal of their power. While it is true that “as long as you are attached to someone or something that you can lose, you are susceptible to suffering”, just saying that is not enough. That suffering is not worth it in every case. Dukkhanirodha remains a cherished goal alongside the others, and it is that for a reason. And so, as the “religious” Stoics would say, we do have reason to keep some distance between ourselves and the external goods we cannot control, to not let ourselves get shaken by the vagaries of fortune.
Nathan said:
This post is the first in this series that provoked me to take a look at the notes and bibliography in Hägglund’s book. The scholar in me was curious to see which sources he cites and whether I could detect—just by reading the book’s back matter—what Amod alleges to be Hägglund’s disinterest in the removal of suffering.
Hägglund’s sources are all Western philosophy, theology, social theory, and some history and novels. I may have missed something, since a couple of pages were omitted from the online preview I checked, but I saw only one author cited about Buddhism, as Amod already noted.
Even more noteworthy to me is the absence of any of the huge literature in modern applied psychology that is relevant to relieving suffering (and that in my view is an important source of wisdom). Hägglund cites nothing from the literature of the clinical professions (medicine, nursing, social work, clinical psychology, etc.). I can’t infer too much from his bibliography, but let’s just say that if Hägglund had wanted to write about preventing and alleviating suffering then he certainly failed to cite an important knowledge base about it.
loveofallwisdom said:
Yes, it’s true that Hägglund only cites one author on Buddhism, as I noted before – but Collins was very good and widely read. As a result (as I noted previously), I think Hägglund’s view of Buddhism is actually more accurate overall than that of some career Buddhism scholars.
Re suffering: I’m not sure how much Hägglund needs to refer back to the psychology literature. That literature is all about how we alleviate suffering. If we’ve decided that’s an unworthy goal in the first place, then we don’t need to worry about the methods. I need to be familiar with the psychology literature for my own work, which does take the removal of suffering as a major goal – and I am seeing what a daunting prospect that is. But I’m not sure Hägglund needs to be.
Nathan said:
“If we’ve decided that’s an unworthy goal in the first place, then we don’t need to worry about the methods.” Exactly. I meant that to be implied in my tongue-in-cheek last sentence. The fact that Hägglund cites a bunch of publications by Søren Kierkegaard and cites nothing by, for example, the 20th century’s most highly cited psychotherapist, Carl Rogers, underscores that point. (I’m not endorsing Rogers, whose important work I think has since been superseded; his name is standing in here for the type of literature that’s absent. The latest editions of The Handbook of Psychotherapy Integration and Systems of Psychotherapy: A Transtheoretical Analysis provide good overviews.)
Bernat said:
Thanks Amod. This tackles the issue about “gray areas” that I mentioned in a comment on your first post on Hägglund.