Tags
Advaita Vedānta, Alasdair MacIntyre, Aristotle, conventional/ultimate, drugs, G.W.F. Hegel, Gārgī Vācaknavī, Muhyiddin ibn 'Arabī, mystical experience, Nathan (commenter), nondualism, pramāṇa, Roland Griffiths, Śaṅkara, Thales, Upaniṣads, Zhiyi
I said previously of nondualism, “I’m not sure I can think of any other major philosophical idea that flowered so much in so many different places, more or less independently. I think that gives us prima facie reason to think the nondualists were on to something important.” Nathan reasonably took me to task for this claim in a comment: “Amod seems to overlook that ideas can be successful without being true.”
I don’t think it’s fair to say I overlooked that point: I said the pervasiveness gave us reason prima facie – at first glance – to say think the nondualists were on to something. That doesn’t mean nondualism is true, and I didn’t say that it was. Second glances might reveal something different. And where I think Nathan is right is in asking us to take those second glances. Is nondualism widespread for a reason other than its being true?
I think the question is particularly important because the rationale given for nondualism does often come down to mystical experience of some sort. Sufis like ibn ‘Arabi, as I understand them, believe that practices like dhikr chanting give one an experience of the unity of being (wahdat al-wujūd). More recently the exciting work of Roland Griffiths and other psychologists has used psilocybin to experimentally induce mystical experiences; the subjects of these experiences report a strong sense of the unity of all things, into which they merge.
The latter point is particularly inviting to a skeptic. If drugs can induce an experience of unity, doesn’t that indicate that that experience is a hallucination, comparable to a fever dream – a perceptual error with nothing to do with reality?
To that I say: not so fast. It could be that the psilocybin makes people see something that isn’t real. But it could also be that it makes them see something that is real! Those who have the experience do typically report a high level of confidence that what they saw was real, and that matters. But the skeptics are right that the experience itself – and for that matter the confidence – is not sufficient to indicate the reality of what was perceived in it.
What is sufficient? To answer that question we need to turn back to good old-fashioned epistemology: our other tools for telling true from false. What do we count as a pramāṇa, a valid means of knowledge? Anyone who asks that question nearly always admits that perception is indeed a means of knowledge: it can lead us to error, yes, but it also often leads us to truth. That snake we see could be a rope – but it could also actually be a snake. When psilocybin or dhikr lead us to perceive the unity of all things, is that perception correct?
Typically when we want to ask whether is a perception is correct, we verify it with another perception. Is that a rope or a snake? Look at it more closely (being careful not to get bitten if it is a snake). Did I smell gas in the kitchen? Check the burners to see if they’re on. But that does not seem an appropriate means of verification in this case. Even if one can seek different means to mystical experience – it is possible, after all, to take psilocybin and practice dhikr – if one of those turned out to be a mere error induced by a change in brain chemistry, there’s a good chance the other one was too.
So what then is a good way to verify whether the world actually is nondual? Here, I think, it matters a great deal that, as I noted in the earlier post, most nondual philosophers actually don’t cite mystical experience as the main justification for nondualism; indeed, as in Śaṅkara’s case, they often don’t cite mystical experience as a justification for nondualism at all. Many of Śaṅkara’s own justifications are scriptural, but that won’t persuade anyone who does not share his faith in the Upaniṣads. Yet Śaṅkara is in debate with Buddhists who do not share that faith, and so he must also make logical arguments why everything must be one. He is far from alone in that. And I think it is the logical case for and against nondualism that can give us the most reliable guide to whether nondualism really is the most accurate way to talk about ultimate reality.
One way logical inquiry explores the possible truth of nondualism is in the very old quest for a first explanation, a quest that goes back at least to the Bṛhadāraṇyaka Upaniṣad (circa 700 BCE, according to Patrick Olivelle). Centuries before Thales would look for an originating principle of all things and discern that it must be water, Gārgī Vācaknavī (one of the few major female characters in early philosophical literature) also observed that “this world is woven back and forth on water”. But Gārgī made this observation only to ask the next question: “on what, then, is water woven back and forth?” The sage Yajñāvalkya replied it was woven on air – to which of course Gārgī asked what the air is woven on. The sequence of recursive questions (“and what is that woven on?”) continues for a while, until Gārgī asks what the worlds of Prajāpati the creator are woven on, and Yajñāvalka names braḥman, that supreme principle that later Vedāntic tradition would identify as the ultimate. Gārgī asks one more time what braḥman is woven on, and Yajñāvalkya tells her “Don’t ask too many questions, Gārgī, or your head will shatter apart!”
That, of course, is a completely unsatisfying answer. But Gārgī’s questioning shows us how, in India and in Greece, inquiry into the nature of things winds up being a search for a first principle. Where will that search end up, if not with a huffy dismissal that the questioner is asking too many questions? It could end up in an infinite regress (turtles all the way down), but when one is asking for ultimate explanations such a regress poses its own problems: as MacIntyre argues, the infinite regress must then itself be explained. For MacIntyre, the series of questions “can terminate only with a being, not itself a member of the series, which makes it the case that this particular series exists.” This gets us to some sort of ultimate as a first principle and first explanation. It does not necessarily get us to nondualism per se – it could be Sirhindī’s “all is from him” – but it gets us somewhere close.
Coming from a different angle, the key test that logic most often applies is coherence. How well does a given idea fit with the other ideas we already take to be true? As always, contradictions are bad (even for Mādhyamikas). But short of actual contradictions there are also what Aristotle would call puzzles (aporiai): places where we perceive apparent contradictions that might not actually be such on a closer look. Getting to truth involves resolving these puzzles, though there are typically so many that we can’t get at all of them.
In my case, one of the driving puzzles is that I have found myself endorsing a position of two truths, in a manner that brings together Wilfrid Sellars and classical Buddhism. But such a position immediately raises the question: what is the relationship between the two? Hegel would have argued that, if we are seeking a most fundamental explanation, then it is that relationship itself that must constitute that explanation. (And so Hegel himself ends up in a certain kind of nondualism, with Spirit as the ultimate.) In China the Tiantai thinker Zhiyi posited a “middle truth” to relate conventional and ultimate, without making the ultimate more fundamental as Hegel does – but it seems to me that this just makes the problem knottier, for now we have to address the relationship between three truths and not only two. There are at least some puzzles that get resolved if one posits a single ultimate and provides reasons why explanation should terminate with that ultimate. Additional puzzles then arise: what is the relationship between that ultimate itself and that which it explains? (I think such a problem may underlie both Plato’s so-called Third Man Argument and Rāmānuja’s critique of Śaṅkara.) I do not by any means think that I have reached a satisfactory resolution to these questions. Yet the logical arguments pointing to an ultimate do give me some reason to think that when the mystics feel certain they have encountered an ultimate reality, we have some reason to believe them. And that the worldwide pervasiveness of nondualism is not just a pervasive error.
Amod, it strikes me that this question is ultimately a question about mereology—the relationships of parts to wholes. From that vantage point, it never makes sense to say “only the whole really exists” or “only the parts really exist.” Things can be taken apart and looked at as parts, or seen together as parts of a whole. Both ways of looking at things have their advantages and disadvantages, depending on our purposes at the moment. Looking at things qua parts is usally how scientific investigations must proceed, because otherwise the number of interacting processes becomes too dizzyingly complex to analyze. On the other hand, looking at only the parts misses some larger questions about the functioning of the whole. When it comes to biology we may understand all the component parts of organisms, yet really have no final conception of how organisms self-organize, self-create, and have purposes. Similarly, an intuition of our larger connection to the whole possibly has meaningful spiritual implications for our lives, but this sense of connection is, as Dewey insists, an act of imagination (in a positive sense of the word) rather than just the discovery of facts laying about in the universe waiting to be discovered.
Great thought, Seth. It brings up a big question around nondualism that I’m not sure I’ve really tackled: does the ultimate have parts? I think it’s that question that separates the Neoplatonists from Aristotle on one hand, and Śaṅkara from Rāmānuja on the other – the former in each pair answering no and the latter answering yes, and I think you’re siding with the latter. For the former, I think the ultimate may be beyond parts; I think that might be especially true for more Buddhist-leaning nondualists where the ultimate is something like emptiness, a Zero rather than a One.
Amod, the question here isn’t whether wholes or parts “really exist” apart from minds that think about them, but that wholes and parts are how human minds can alternatively construe things, much like alternations in perceiving a Necker cube. Obviously, the non-human universe does not concern itself with parts and wholes. It is just nature doing what nature does.
I agree the issue here isn’t in/dependence from minds. Rather, the question I’m talking about is whether the relationship between the many and the one(/zero) is best conceived as a part-whole relationship in the first place. I think Śaṅkara, Nāgārjuna and Plotinus would all agree that it is not.
I enjoyed this post, I’m glad it addressed (to some degree) my objection that Amod mentioned, and I think Seth is on to something in his comment about the usefulness of an analysis that includes both wholes and parts. Mario Bunge called such an analysis systemism, which he distinguished from atomism and holism, and he disliked holism for being “hostile to analysis”. Similarly to Bunge’s complaint about holism, I think nondualists could run into an epistemic wall if they remain satisfied with saying that everything is a whole and parts are mere illusions, and thereby obstruct inquiry into a better systemic analysis. (I’m not enough of a scholar of nondualism to know whether nondualism has ever been an epistemic obstruction in this way; I’m just speculating very generally here.)
But having pointed out that potential weakness of nondualism, I might as well admit that as far as I know, everything is a whole (the universe), and not a random confusion of parts appearing and disappearing without cause, so I can agree that nondualists were on to something important about that. But an acceptance that everything is such a whole may be a universal presupposition of systematic inquiry and not a unique characteristic of nondualism! Furthermore, the concept of the whole doesn’t explain anything apart from the systematization of knowledge in which the concept of the whole is a part, so the important question for me is: How skillful is that systematization of knowledge and how can we improve it? The title of an article by Nicholas Rescher comes to mind: “Inference from the best systematization”, Mind & Society, 15(2), 2016, 147–154. Not inference to an ultimate first explanation, but inference from a current best systematization.
Here as with Seth, the question for me is about whether the nondual ultimate is best characterized as a whole with parts. Certainly Śaṅkara would say that the world’s perceived plurality is illusion (and I think Nāgārjuna and Śāntideva would join him on that), and because of that I think part/whole is not the way they would conceive the relationship between that plurality and the ultimate. I think that position does obstruct further inquiry into systemic analysis, but they would view that as a feature and not a bug: they think the most valuable pursuit is not an attempt to think the world, as Aristotle does, but in some respect to think one’s way out of it.
It’s helpful for me to have this exchange, though. It reminds me that if I am to remain a philosopher who believes worldly goals are valuable, that suggests I would need to lean more to a Rāmānuja-Aristotle sense of the part-whole relationship.
Yes, something similar came to my mind about how different the terms or categories of those Indian thinkers were. Another term that may be worth throwing into the conversation is perspectivism. In perspectivism, the world’s plurality as perceived by an agent is not an illusion but a perspective. Today we have pretty sophisticated explanations of perspectival appearances thanks to our scientific systematizations, but I imagine that a deep explanation of such varied appearances would have been a much more difficult problem for those earlier Indian thinkers.
Amod, I think a fundamental confusion concerning mereology afflicts all of Buddhist thinking. When it comes to nonduality, only the whole is real and the parts are illusory. When it comes to personhood, only the skandhas are real and the person is illusory. I don’t think you can argue both ways. And yes, Nathan, I agree, perspectivism seems exacly the right term to throw into this conversation.
And one final point on mereology. I’m not sure what Sankara and Nagarjuna might say regarding the existence of parts, but Fazang talks a great deal about the relationships between parts and wholes in his rafter dialogue…
Pingback: No opposite for the ultimate | Love of All Wisdom