The Sigālovāda Sutta might be my least favourite sutta in the Pali Canon.
There is relatively little that the Pali texts say on “ethics” in a modern Western sense of interpersonal action-guiding; much of the specific instructions on action are found in vinaya, legal texts for the conduct of monks. The Sigālovāda is relatively unusual in providing guidance for action to lay householders. For that reason, a number of secondary writers on Buddhist ethics regard it as as a valuable guide for Buddhist ethical conduct.
I do not.
I recognize that the Sigālovāda is in the scriptures and therefore should not just be wished away: for those of us who have faith in a tradition, it is important to wrestle with what we find most unappealing, because that can be what we learn the most from. Yet that faith should not be blind; we should not simply swallow the tradition’s words whole irrespective of what we have learned in other areas of life. To act in that latter way is to be a fundamentalist, in a way that I think does justice to both the self-identified and the pejorative senses of that word. I think it is important to keep some distance from the scriptures that portray an unscientific worldview (this is where Bultmann is helpful), and likewise from those that recommend inferior treatment for women or for queer or trans people. In my view, the Sigālovāda is in a similar category of works not to be taken as direct advice without heavy reinterpretation.
I say this because the Sigālovāda’s recommended lifestyle seems to me like a vicious mean. The Sigālovāda’s householder is not a monk, and therefore deprives himself of the deep and intense opportunities for self-cultivation that are available to a monk. That much seems reasonable: most of us see value in pursuits of life that are not monastic, and so there’s appeal in pursuing a kammatic Buddhism that recognizes the non-monastic life as valuable.
The problem with the Sigālovāda is that it strips that life, the household life, of a great deal of its value! I look at the life described there and I think: what does this life have to recommend itself over being a monk? Some of the sutta’s prohibitions are understandable: on gambling, for example. And while I don’t follow its prohibition on alcohol, that prohibition is found in plenty of other places. But the Sigālovāda also tells one not to sleep even until sunrise, let alone afterwards. And most alarmingly, it also includes a prohibition on “frequenting theatrical shows”.
There are, young householder, these six evil consequences in frequenting theatrical shows. He is ever thinking: where is there dancing? where is there singing? where is there music? where is there recitation? where is there playing with cymbals? where is there pot-blowing?
The reasoning here is understandable: if you take pleasure in singing and dancing and music, you will want to do more of it, and that will preoccupy your thoughts in a way that can lead to craving. That is perhaps in the nature of any pleasure: whatever enjoyable thing one does, the pleasure typically leads one to want more of it. So, given that suffering comes from craving, there is some reason to treat pleasures and enjoyments as suspect.
I understand and even sympathize with that chain of reasoning. But, if one is going to follow it through to its conclusion, it seems to me that one needs to renounce and become a monk. If one really is going to avoid worldly pleasures – not even drinking and gambling, but simple music and theatre – on the grounds that they lead to more craving, then what benefits in the household life are even left? (The Sigālovāda itself does not cast particular suspicion on the satisfactions of having children, but there are other places in the Canon that do: most notably, when the Buddha had a son, he named him Rāhula, “fetter”.) It seems to me that one should fish or cut bait, so to speak. If one is really ready to treat all pleasures as suspect, one should become a monk; if one is not willing to go all that way, one needs a life that makes room for pleasures like dancing and theatre.
H.L. Seneviratne, in his excellent The Work of Kings, notes how monks in colonial Sri Lanka elevated the Sigālovāda Sutta to a higher status in the canon than it had previously had. They performed a similar elevation on the Five Precepts, one that is visible in our modern tendency to include the Five Precepts in most introductions to Buddhism even though they are encountered less frequently in the suttas than the Four Noble Truths and the Noble Eightfold Path. These elevations occurred for a very specific reason: these monks were Victorian men who had absorbed the ideals of their Victorian English colonial occupiers. And the austere moral discipline of the Sigālovāda, with its sustained attacks on “idleness”, fit the work-obsessed Victorian worldview like a glove. One could even argue that the Sigālovāda’s attacks on the theatre allowed the monks to one-up Victorian prudery, taking it one step further than the English Victorians themselves would go. The brilliance of the Sigālovāda in this context was that it did not go the next step beyond that, and advocate traditional Buddhist monasticism! That would not do, for monks, in addition to reeking of popery, are not productive, not industrious. As Thomas Tweed noted (and as I discuss at more length in my Disengaged Buddhism article), the Victorians considered the world’s Buddhist places to be “asleep”, lacking “energy”, for their citizens did not allowing the emerging global capitalism to make sufficient use of their labour power. By Victorian standards, the Sigālovāda’s mean was the virtuous one: between the indolence of the idle gambler on one hand, and the indolence of the unproductive monk on the other.
Fortunately, however, we are now over a century away from the Victorian era. We are able to ask: what was all that hard work for? We can note with Hägglund that selling our labour power is in the realm of necessity rather than the realm of freedom; industriousness is a means, not an end. So what are the ends? The removal of suffering is a worthy end in and of itself, and if it is the only end that we seek, then the right option is monasticism. But if we do seek other ends – as I think is a good idea – then those other ends should include aesthetic pleasures like those of music and theatre.
Pingback: The Sigālovāda’s vicious mean – The Indian Philosophy Blog
Donna L Brown said:
Good post. I especially like your comment that this sutra became popular as part of the transition to Buddhist modernism in Sri Lanka, in which Victorian mores were adopted by Buddhists. Sri Lankan Buddhist modernism then became influential in the development of other forms of Buddhist modernism and the sutra’s popularity spread –perhaps parallel to the Kalama sutta and its increase in popularity around the same time because it met a modern need. Maybe we need a post listing sutras Buddhist modernists like, and why!! Another thought, unrelated: I wonder if one reason theatre was denigrated at the time the sutra appeared is that it included courtesans and sexual themes–maybe it was the pornography of its day… If we go by what Augustine says, this was the content of Greek theatre and why Augustine opposed it.
Amod Lele said:
Yeah, the question of who likes which suttas when is one that I’ve seen surprisingly little attention paid to, overall. I recall someone using the concept of the “practical canon” – the texts that actually get quoted and learned from, as opposed to the ones that sit in the texts getting ignored.
Re sexual themes, I suppose it’s possible, but if that were the case I don’t know why the sutta wouldn’t just come out and say so. It’s not as if they’re shy about talking about sex elsewhere in the canon (man, that vinaya!)
Donna L Brown said:
Well, one reason why they might not say so is that “theatre” may have been defined to mean that then, unlike now where “theatre” includes a range of material, not just sexual by any means. Recall that up through Elizabethan times in England, theatre was not respectable– the word itself implied a certain bawdiness (as in ancient Greece). If the word itself means “bawdiness” there would be no need to add that the content is often sexual. That said, I have no idea of the social context in which the sutta was written; I only note that historically theatre has often been perceived as bawdy and morally dubious. By the way, I am not disputing your point about the sutta as unreasonably imposing semi-monastic strictures on lay people. But it IS possible that theatre was denounced not because it was pleasurable but because the pleasures it offered were deemed outside the bounds of proper lay morality.
David J Meskill said:
Hi Amod,
Jason Clower alerted me to your blog, and I’m glad to have found it. I wanted to comment on your post from 11/29/20, but the comment function was not available (at least for me).
Your argument about al-Ghazali was new to me and quite interesting. One question occurred to me. I was familiar with Ghazali as someone who had contributed to the blunting of the “scientific” spirit in the Islamic world (at least, this is what the comparative sociologist of science Toby Huff has claimed). If Ghazali’s occasionalism had that effect in the Islamic world, how could Ockham’s and Hume’s fallibilism play a constructive role in the growth of western science? Any thoughts, or suggestions of something to read on this?
Amod Lele said:
Hi David – welcome! Please give Jason my regards. Yes, the blog unfortunately is set to disable comments on posts more than a few months old (including that one), because otherwise they would attract a lot of spammers.
Regarding Ghazali, I’m no expert, and what I say should be treated as speculation. I’m not familiar with Huff, but I could imagine a case that Ghazali’s more scripturalist approach might have discouraged scientific inquiry. I think the thing is that his fallibilism only went so far: we human beings are fallible, but God and his scripture are not. Ockham, I think, actually took a similar approach. But by the time we get to Hume, even scripture is something put into question – in a way that would likely have got Hume beheaded if he’d lived in Ockham’s day.
As far as what to read, that’s a great question and I’m afraid I’m coming up blank. In writing that post I cobbled together stuff from a lot of different places, like the IEP entry on Malebranche. I’m not aware of someone who’s foregrounded the question in any detail – I would love it if someone did!
David J Meskill said:
Thanks, Amod. That makes sense. I will continue reading your stuff and occasionally commenting.
I’ll pass on your greetings to Jason. We were both first-year proctors at Harvard in the 2000s.
Amod Lele said:
Ah, OK – then I would have overlapped with you in grad school as well, though I don’t think we met at the time. I look forward to your future comments!
David J Meskill said:
Actually, a question just popped into my head. I teach the first part of a great books course that has traditionally been western-focused. Last year, in the interest of making the course more of a global great books class, I introduced some new units, including one on Neo-Confucianism. We did this right after a unit on Dante. I thought (and still think) that there enough commonalities between the Scholastics and Neo-Confucians (both defending a kind of virtue ethics? both incorporating elements from different traditions [Christian and Greek/Confucian, Buddhist, Daoist]) to make it worthwhile – but the first time around, especially on Zoom, was not a big success. So I’m thinking about major revisions.
Can you suggest NC readings that might go well with Dante/Scholasticism or, at least, might be relatively accessible for students with no background in Asian religion or philosophy? Do you know of anybody who incorporates NC in a global great books sequence?
Thanks for any assistance you can give!
Amod Lele said:
Hm, also a tough question. Overall, I think there has not been nearly enough accessible stuff written on Neo-Confucianism. I was impressed by the selections (from Zhu Xi and others) in Van Norden and Tiwald’s Readings in Later Chinese Philosophy; that section is probably the best intro to Neo-Confucianism I know. It might also be helpful to comparisons with the Scholastics in that several of those readings are in the form of commentary. So that’s probably what I’d go with?
David J Meskill said:
Thank you, Amod. That’s very helpful. I have been watching some of Van Norden’s lectures on youtube and finding them very helpful. I will definitely get my hands on the book you mention. Thanks again – David.
Justin Whitaker said:
Hia Amod!
Long-time reader, infrequent commenter :)
As promised, I’ve written a quasi-response (only quasi, as the post is largely just a reexamination of the sutta for myself, and not at all a pointed response to your writing).
Alluded to, but not well-articulated in my piece, is the idea that Buddhism values more than just the end goal of awakening. As a path (marga/magga), there is value in every step forward we can take and different texts will offer advice reflecting that range of values.
The focus of Buddhist ethics is not so much on finding an Aristotelian mean, but in making progress along the path. For a person like Sigala, and surely many of us today, progress could be best accomplished by reducing (or foregoing) certain of life’s little pleasures. Perhaps no longer “frequenting theatrical performances” could mean going a bit less often, using the new free time to study or practice or help friends. Seeing the benefit of those over the theatre, perhaps Sigala would give it up altogether in much the same way some of us today give up certain social media platforms or their television sets.
The teaching, like so many of the Buddha’s conversations, does not come across as a list of “prohibitions” so much as advice from a mentor or wise friend. Take it or leave it (and we so often see the Buddha’s interlocutors shrug and walk away), it is offered as the Buddha’s clear insight into what is beneficial and what leads to suffering.
My article:
https://www.buddhistdoor.net/features/sitting-with-sigala-a-modern-laypersonrsquos-buddhist-ethics
Amod Lele said:
Hey Justin – it’s really good to hear from you again. Between this and the article I think there’s a lot more to say, so I’m hoping to make a whole post of my own about it in the future.
Pingback: Reinterpreting the Sigālovāda’s prohibition on theatre | Love of All Wisdom
Pingback: Reinterpreting the Sigālovāda’s prohibition on theatre – The Indian Philosophy Blog