Tags
20th century, autobiography, Canada, Charles Taylor, Douglas Adams, G.W.F. Hegel, George Grant, James Doull, John Watson, José Enrique Rodó, Queen's University, Robert Sibley, United States
Hegel wrote about Canada just once, in the Lectures on the Philosophy of History, and what he said comes down to: mostly harmless. His main concern in that passage is the future power of the United States; having noted that the poor organization of the American colonies prevented them from conquering Canada, he then adds that Canada and Mexico “present no serious threat” to the US, and then moves on. It is scarcely more consideration than Voltaire’s dismissal of Canada as “a few acres of snow”; like the fictional Hitchhiker’s Guide to the Galaxy discussing Earth, Hegel pauses on Canada only long enough to say “you don’t need to worry about it.”
And yet, as Robert Sibley notes in beginning his fascinating Northern Spirits, English Canadian philosophers have had a deep, abiding and continuing interest in Hegel, unrequited as it may be – an interest not generally shared by other countries in the anglophone West. Canadian Hegelianism turns out to be its own philosophical tradition – one that’s played a significant role in my own philosophical formation. It is only in the 21st century that people like Sibley have started writing about this Canadian Hegelianism, but it’s been around for longer.
The earliest major figure in Canadian Hegelianism is John Watson (1847-1939). Watson’s interest in Hegel was not unusual for his day: he inherited his Hegelianism directly from his teacher Edward Caird, one of the British Idealists in vogue in the late 19th century. Watson also corresponded with the St. Louis Hegelians and published in their journal. (Did you know there were St. Louis Hegelians?)
Watson taught at Queen’s University, a stone’s throw from my childhood home, and left his mark on it as the head of the philosophy department for nearly fifty years; the main building for humanities and philosophy at Queen’s is named after him to this day. But his ideas lay dormant for a while, and perhaps for good reason. I certainly find Watson’s views rather unsympathetic; he took up Hegel’s holism to argue that Canada had its proper role as a part of the whole that was the British Empire, rather than an independent “little Canada” that could stand on its own. To me he is most interesting as a part of the philosophical culture in the place where I grew up.
The lack of interest in Watson’s ideas after his death reflected a general trend in the first half of the 20th century. The analytic movement in anglophone philosophy tended to discredit Hegel and his followers; thus the British Idealists and St. Louis Hegelians left no real heirs. Even in Canada, there were few significant Hegelian thinkers in the mid-20th century, the one exception being the Hegelian Marxism of C.B. Macpherson. Up to that point, I think, Canadian philosophy’s relationship to Hegel was fairly standard for the English-speaking world.
It is in the late twentieth century that something different started to happen. From about the 1970s onward, arguably the three most important thinkers in Canadian phliosophy all had deep Hegelian influences. This was bucking a global trend. The mainstream of anglophone philosophy around the world remained staunchly dedicated to the analytical approach. In the UK and especially the US, the “continental” dissidents tended to favour the French postmodernism of Derrida and Foucault, defining itself with Heidegger and against Hegel. It’s in the past half-century that Canadian Hegelianism really came to distinguish itself.
The three Canadian thinkers in question are Charles Taylor, George Grant, and James Doull. Taylor likely needs little introduction to a philosophical audience: he is one of the most important philosophers thinking through qualitative individualism (which he calls the ethics of authenticity), as well as the politics of multicultural societies. Grant is not very well known outside of Canada, but within Canada he was one of the leading public intellectuals of the late 20th century, as his Lament for a Nation spoke directly to the perennial English Canadian worry about what exactly Canada is and means.
Doull – a friend of Grant’s – is the least well known of the three, because he wrote very little; his influence carries on above all through his students, a third generation of whom includes the chair of Doull’s old department and the founder of a new university in Georgia. Indirectly he’s also left his stamp on me: before I found Buddhism, my philosophy had been largely Hegelian, in ways that owe a great deal to my lifelong friend who studied in Doull’s department. I would probably be much less of a Hegelian if I were not Canadian.
Taylor, Grant and Doull share a deep Hegelian inheritance with Watson and Macpherson. Taylor began his scholarly career with a book on Hegel that remains one of the best introductions to Hegel’s thought, and came back to Hegel in various ways throughout that career. Doull, always a classicist, focused on Hegel’s oft-neglected classical inheritance, drawing out the ideas of Plato, Aristotle, Augustine and the Neoplatonists in Hegelian terms; the journals Animus and Dionysius carry on his Hegelian approach to the classics. Grant ultimately came to reject Hegel in favour of a more Straussian Platonism, but his early works are deeply Hegelian, in a way reflecting Watson’s direct influence: his grandfather George Monro Grant was the principal of Queen’s University at the time when Watson’s influence there was at its height. And he maintained a continuing interest in Hegel through his friendship with Doull.
Like Watson, all three are concerned with the nature of Canada and its role in the world, and Hegel helps them think this through. Grant takes up Watson’s view that Canada distinguishes itself through being a part of the British Commonwealth, and is pessimistic that in the 20th century Canada largely given this up by becoming closer to the United States. (In that, Watson and Grant have an interesting kinship with the Uruguayan philosopher José Enrique Rodó, who feared the influence of the USA and admired the British monarchy as a bulwark against it.) Doull has the more optimistic view that both Canada and the US still hew to Hegel’s ideal of civic (rather than ethnic) nationalism, Canada managing particularly well by including two founding nations within it. Taylor’s bilingual and bicultural Québec upbringing leads him to think philosophically through Québec nationalism; his concept for doing so is “the politics of recognition“, which he gets from Hegel’s Lordship and Bondage section. In a very Hegelian manner, the three all think about the idea of Canada in ways whose implications go well beyond Canada itself. And this century’s spate of new Canadian books reflecting on Canadian Hegelianism, not just by Sibley but by Robert Meynell, Ian Angus, and Susan Dodd and Neil Robertson, suggest that Canadian Hegelian tradition will continue to flourish in the years ahead.
EDIT (6 Dec 2022): The original version of this post said that Rousseau had called Canada “a few acres of snow”. I meant Voltaire.
Evan Thompson said:
Very nice post. However, I think your historical narrative isn’t quite right. There was a strong presence of significant Hegelian thinkers in Toronto in the mid-twentieth century: the two most notable being Emil Fackenheim at the University of Toronto and Henry Silton Harris at York University. I took Harrris’s year-long course on the Phenomenology of Spirit when I was a graduate student at University of Toronto in the late 80s. It was one of the best courses I took; his lectures were later published as his two-volume work, Hegel’s Ladder. See the book Hegel and Canada: Unity of Opposites for coverage of these scholars: https://utorontopress.com/9781442660663/hegel-and-canada/ These figures also shaped a new generation of philosophers active today in Canada, notably Rebecca Comay at the University of Toronto and John Russon at the University of Guelph.
Amod Lele said:
Thanks! And hm, interesting. I had thought of Fackenheim as being a bit later because he debated Doull (from an anti-Hegelian perspective), but yeah, that was late in his career. I wonder if to some extent it depends how we define “mid-century”? What I’m noticing is that there doesn’t seem to have been much continuity from Watson to the later thinkers, even when those include Fackenheim and Harris.
Kevin O'Meara said:
Pardon the length of this comment, but I wrote my master’s thesis on Hegel’s philosophy of history in the Canadian context, and I figured I’d share a section regarding the ignored components of Hegelianism in late 19th/early 20th century Canada that adds to your discussion here!
John Watson was born in Glasgow, but is known as the first Canadian philosopher to achieve an international reputation, having produced several works broadly about German idealism, with Hegel as a particular focus. In addition to serving as the head of the philosophy department at Queen’s University in Kingston for over 50 years, he introduced the disciplines of Economics, Political Studies, and Psychology to the university, which served as an exemplary model for secular education throughout the country (Queen’s Encyclopedia). David MacGregor (1994) points out that “Watson was the first to claim that Canada was Hegel’s true home, since the Germans had long since abandoned his philosophy.” This was significant not only for detached philosophical speculations of a few academicians, but for the practical development of the settler state’s bureaucracy and intellectual culture. As Elizabeth Trott (2018) notes,
the migration of Watson’s students to the civil service in Ottawa […] was a big part of the development of Canadian customs. Queen’s University staffed the civil service, and almost every student from Queen’s who headed to Ottawa soon after Confederation would have been at some point in Watson’s classes. (p. 197) In 1906, theologian C.T. Scott reported to the head of the Canadian Methodist Church that “I find that nearly every man who has passed through “Queen’s University,” and a coterie who follow this set, are preaching Hegelianism. It is a sad plight” (Carman). This Hegelian plight was to reach deep into the 20th century and beyond.
Hegel’s influence would be further entrenched, this time in the Canadian legal system, by Richard Haldane, who has been dubbed the ‘Step-father of the Canadian Constitution’ (Vaughan, 2011) and the ‘unknown father of Confederation’ (Campbell, 2020). Haldane served as Lord Chancellor and member of the Judicial Committee of the Privy Council from 1911 until his death in 1928, and made enormously consequential legal decisions on cases regarding the division of powers between the federal and provincial governments under the British North America Act of 1867. According to Wexler (1984), he had so much influence that “thanks to Haldane, the Canadian constitution is taken to be a list of the things that governments can do” (p. 646). Haldane gave very restrictive readings to both the “peace, order and good government” power of the federal government, as well as the federal criminal law power, setting the precedent for the internationally unique sovereignty and set of powers given to the provinces within the federation (Wexler, 1984).
Wexler (1984) indicates that “all through his busy career in law and politics, [Haldane] wrote philosophy as a kind of ‘sideline’, publishing numerous books and articles on a wide variety of philosophical subjects” (p. 626), including articles entitled ‘Hegel and his Recent Critics’ in 1888 and ‘Hegel’ in 1895. According to Vaughan (2011), Haldane’s “turn to the study of law was a direct outcome of his Hegelian philosophy” (p. 40), and in turn Hegel’s “philosophy of historicism entered into the legal life of Canada by way of his Scottish pupil’s conscious appropriation of his ‘philosophy of right’ and history” (p. xii). In his studies, Haldane saw “that Hegel was speaking to the monarchical core of the British Empire, a truly ‘dominant people’, providentially entrusted with the great mission of fulfilling the Absolute Spirit of freedom. It was as if Hegel were urging young British philosophers to comprehend their role in the universalising spirit of freedom portrayed throughout the British Empire”. (Vaughan, 2011, p. 33) As a result, it has been argued that Haldane’s decisions regarding early constitutional law in Canada have contributed an enormous amount of Hegelian influence to subsequent legal decisions, particularly pertaining to the self-determination of provinces.
Amod Lele said:
Thanks, Kevin! (And welcome.) This is helping me see that Canadian Hegelianism goes even deeper than I’d imagined myself.
Amod Lele said:
… also, Kevin, where can I get a copy of your master’s thesis?
Polemarchus said:
Fascinating, this. I hadn’t known about Watson. Too bad Watson Hall is so titanically ugly.
Amod Lele said:
I think you’d like Watson a lot – you’d probably find the overall tone of his politics a lot more appealing than I do. The State in Peace and War is his major work; consider giving it a look when you have a chance.
Nathan said:
I’m reminded of the Argentine-Canadian philosopher Mario Bunge, who lived the latter half of his life in Montreal and had some sharp words about Hegel’s scientific deficiencies. I read Hegel’s Lectures on the Philosophy of History for a college course, and like Bunge I was not impressed.
Bunge did, however, concede that Hegel raised “important problems”. I’m interested in the problem of the development of knowledge in general and how it works (historical and developmental epistemology and psychology), in which the concept of dialectic remains useful to some degree, apart from Hegelianism as a package: see, for example, the dialectical constructivist epistemology of Juan Pascual-Leone at York University, a Canadian non-Hegelian dialectical epistemology.
Amod Lele said:
Bunge was teaching at McGill when I was there, though I never actually took a course with him. I vaguely recall reading something of his in a sociological theory class and not being very impressed with Bunge myself – but that was a quarter-century ago and I don’t remember any detail.
Nathan said:
Amod, I’d say there’s not much overlap between your project and Bunge’s project, and I doubt you would have liked a course of his. There is basically nothing in his work that is relevant to articulating a qualitative individualism. In Bunge’s memoir he mentions that Charles Taylor helped him immigrate to Canada and that he liked Taylor, but it’s clear Bunge didn’t have any interest in what Taylor was doing, nor would Taylor have had any use for Bunge’s work.
I looked at Bunge’s page on RateMyProfessors.com (unfortunately it’s gone now and I didn’t save it to the Internet Archive, though I saved my own copy) with course reviews from 2002–2008 when he would have been in his 80s and still teaching at McGill, and the reviews were a hilarious mix of fans and haters. “First I hated him, now I think he’s great. Very old.” “This man is a god!” “One of the most pedantic and dogmatic people in the department.” “Wow! This man is a genius. His assertions are clear, and his points concise. It is only tough to argue with him because most of the time he is right.” “Bunge is smarter than Einstein and more dogmatic than Trotsky.” “This class be ****’in. Enjoy the fight.”
Pingback: Mini-Heap | Daily Nous
Pingback: A very brief survey of Latin American philosophy | Love of All Wisdom