Tags

,

Probably the most widely quoted passage from Ibram X. Kendi’s How to Be an Antiracist is this one:

What’s the problem with being “not racist”? It is a claim that signifies neutrality: “I am not a racist, but neither am I aggressively against racism.” But there is no neutrality in the racism struggle. The opposite of “racist” isn’t “not racist.” It is “antiracist.” What’s the difference? One endorses either the idea of a racial hierarchy as a racist, or racial equality as an antiracist. One either believes problems are rooted in groups of people, as a racist, or locates the roots of problems in power and policies, as an antiracist. One either allows racial inequities to persevere, as a racist, or confronts racial inequities, as an anti-racist. There is no in-between safe space of “not racist.” The claim of “not racist” neutrality is a mask for racism. (9)

Let us suppose that one goes into reading this paragraph believing – as I do, as most people used to, as most people quite possibly still do – that it is indeed possible to be neutral, to be simply not racist. What reason does this passage then provide to believe anything different? What argument is being made for the claim that one cannot be neutral, beyond the bare assertion, beyond the equivalent of stomping one’s shoe on the table? As far as I can tell, there is none. You just get the assertion that “‘not racist’ neutrality is a mask for racism”, and you’re expected to swallow it whole without any criticism.

So from this book I get no reason to believe that it is impossible to be not racist. Rather, I get reason to believe the contrary, that it is possible. After all, Kendi admits that

Race and racism are power constructs of the modern world. For roughly two hundred thousand years, before race and racism were constructed in the fifteenth century, humans saw color but did not group the colors into continental races, did not commonly attach negative and positive characteristics to those colors and rank the races to justify racial inequity, to reinforce racist power and policy. Racism is not even six hundred years old. (238)

So let’s consider the people of the world six hundred years ago. Clearly, on the acccount of this paragraph, they did not “endorse the idea of a racial hierarchy” as racists; they did not have the concept of a racial hierarchy available to endorse. But they also could not have endorsed the idea of racial equality! For if the concept of race had not been constructed, there was nothing that could have been equal or unequal. Six hundred years ago, when race and racism did not exist, it was not possible for the people of this world, on Kendi’s own account, to be either racist or anti-racist. Therefore, they could only have been – not racist.

Therefore, on Kendi’s own account of world history, the “in-between safe space of ‘not racist'” must be at least conceptually possible. That safe space existed in the past – and it can be imagined in the future. In BU’s newsletter Kendi himself said:

it was very difficult for people to believe that slavery, 45 years later, would be no more, just as I think there are many people today who can’t imagine that there could be a nation without racism and inequality.

Kendi implies that he himself can imagine a nation without racism. But that implies that it must also be possible to be not racist at that point in the future. For it makes no sense to be antiracist if there is no racism left to be anti! So the claim that “There is no in-between safe space of ‘not racist'” must refer only to the current situation, in which racism and racial inequities exist. And therefore in order for the claim to make any sense, one must qualify it as something like: “as long as racial inequities exist, one either allows them to persevere, as a racist, or confronts them as an antiracist.”

But we don’t have good reason to believe even that qualified claim. The implication of excluding the “not racist” middle here is that, by not confronting racial inequalities as an antiracist, one is thereby “allowing them to persevere”, and that implies that one is a racist. It is effectively an application of the common aphorism that “if you are not part of the solution, you are part of the problem.” The aphorism does not merely deny the possibility of a neutral stance: it also claims that it’s not enough to take a stance against the problem, one must actually be part of the solution, actively work to solve the problem – or else one is a part of it.

But is this aphorism really accurate? Racism is a problem today, I’ll agree with Kendi on that. But as I write this, there is also a civil war raging in the Sudan that has killed tens of thousands and displaced millions. That too is a problem. I am not confronting that problem, and as far as I know, neither is Kendi. But Kendi’s logic in this passage is that those who do not confront a problem thereby allow it to persevere, and thereby are effectively supporting that problem.

Therefore, by Kendi’s logic, he and I are “allowing” the war in Sudan to “persevere” – and we are therefore supporters of that war. We are not confronting the persecution of Rohingya refugees in Burma; therefore, we are allowing it to persevere, and we are therefore supporters of that persecution. We are not part of any of these solutions – and therefore, by Kendi’s “no safe space” logic, we are part of all of these problems. One must be a part of the solution to any and all problems in the world, including climate change, gun violence, famine, emerging diseases, biodiversity loss, nuclear proliferation, desertification, AIDS, cyberbullying, sexual harassment, human trafficking, terrorism, inflation, water scarcity, peak oil, cancer, heart disease, traffic accidents, the teen mental health crisis, soil erosion, acid rain, and the Great Pacific Garbage Patch – or else one is a part of each of them. For one who does not confront them allows them to persevere, and by that inaction supports them.

Putin-led destruction in Ukraine. We are not obligated to prioritize fighting American racism over fighting this. (Adobe stock photo.)

Theoretically, Kendi could resist this conclusion by naming something special about racism as a problem, something that means one must actively be a part of the solution to that specific problem, in a way that one does not need to be a part of the solution to any of the others. But remarkably, he never does this. He talks rarely if ever about issues other than social inequality, so there’s no comparison with those other issues to be made. Rather, all he does is make a specific rhetorical move – the racist/antiracist division – that privileges racism over all other problems. It tars neutral people with the serious accusation of racism, an accusation that can get you ostracized or fired. The implication is: “If you’re not a part of the racism solution, you’re part of the racism problem – but you’re free to not be a part of the solution to any other problem. This is the one that matters.” “You can’t be not racist” follows Nathan Robinson’s unjustified conceit that everyone must be an activist – and makes it worse by specifying further that everyone must be an activist for this specific cause. The effect of the “can’t be not racist” rhetoric, on people who haven’t thought about it, is to make them think, without reason, that they must put racism first: they must prioritize that problem over climate change, over economic inequality, over gun violence, over everything else.

Because of course we can’t actually be working to solve every possible problem the world has. There are people who try to do so: they’re called burnouts. If one is to be an effective activist for the causes one cares about most, one must be active in one’s support of those specific causes. One must focus, one must pick one’s battles. An anti-racist activist can be against climate change and nuclear proliferation and Putin’s invasion of Ukraine, but if she tries to confront all of those different issues, she will weaken her own anti-racist activism. So likewise, a climate activist or an activist for socialism needs to focus on those causes, not on actively confronting racism. By Kendi’s standards, that makes them racists.

Kendi tries to defend that conclusion, in part, by claiming that “racist” is a merely descriptive term, not a pejorative. I’ll address what’s wrong with that view next time.